登陆注册
15451600000014

第14章 13

Perhaps enough has been said about the proof of necessity, how it comes about and how it differs from the proof of a simple statement.

We proceed to discuss that which is possible, when and how and by what means it can be proved. I use the terms 'to be possible' and 'the possible' of that which is not necessary but, being assumed, results in nothing impossible. We say indeed ambiguously of the necessary that it is possible. But that my definition of the possible is correct is clear from the phrases by which we deny or on the contrary affirm possibility. For the expressions 'it is not possible to belong', 'it is impossible to belong', and 'it is necessary not to belong' are either identical or follow from one another; consequently their opposites also, 'it is possible to belong', 'it is not impossible to belong', and 'it is not necessary not to belong', will either be identical or follow from one another. For of everything the affirmation or the denial holds good. That which is possible then will be not necessary and that which is not necessary will be possible.

It results that all premisses in the mode of possibility are convertible into one another. I mean not that the affirmative are convertible into the negative, but that those which are affirmative in form admit of conversion by opposition, e.g. 'it is possible to belong' may be converted into 'it is possible not to belong', and 'it is possible for A to belong to all B' into 'it is possible for A to belong to no B' or 'not to all B', and 'it is possible for A to belong to some B' into 'it is possible for A not to belong to some B'.

And similarly the other propositions in this mode can be converted.

For since that which is possible is not necessary, and that which is not necessary may possibly not belong, it is clear that if it is possible that A should belong to B, it is possible also that it should not belong to B: and if it is possible that it should belong to all, it is also possible that it should not belong to all. The same holds good in the case of particular affirmations: for the proof is identical. And such premisses are affirmative and not negative; for 'to be possible' is in the same rank as 'to be', as was said above.

Having made these distinctions we next point out that the expression 'to be possible' is used in two ways. In one it means to happen generally and fall short of necessity, e.g. man's turning grey or growing or decaying, or generally what naturally belongs to a thing (for this has not its necessity unbroken, since man's existence is not continuous for ever, although if a man does exist, it comes about either necessarily or generally). In another sense the expression means the indefinite, which can be both thus and not thus, e.g. an animal's walking or an earthquake's taking place while it is walking, or generally what happens by chance: for none of these inclines by nature in the one way more than in the opposite.

That which is possible in each of its two senses is convertible into its opposite, not however in the same way: but what is natural is convertible because it does not necessarily belong (for in this sense it is possible that a man should not grow grey) and what is indefinite is convertible because it inclines this way no more than that. Science and demonstrative syllogism are not concerned with things which are indefinite, because the middle term is uncertain; but they are concerned with things that are natural, and as a rule arguments and inquiries are made about things which are possible in this sense. Syllogisms indeed can be made about the former, but it is unusual at any rate to inquire about them.

These matters will be treated more definitely in the sequel; our business at present is to state the moods and nature of the syllogism made from possible premisses. The expression 'it is possible for this to belong to that' may be understood in two senses: 'that' may mean either that to which 'that' belongs or that to which it may belong; for the expression 'A is possible of the subject of B' means that it is possible either of that of which B is stated or of that of which B may possibly be stated. It makes no difference whether we say, A is possible of the subject of B, or all B admits of A. It is clear then that the expression 'A may possibly belong to all B' might be used in two senses. First then we must state the nature and characteristics of the syllogism which arises if B is possible of the subject of C, and A is possible of the subject of B. For thus both premisses are assumed in the mode of possibility; but whenever A is possible of that of which B is true, one premiss is a simple assertion, the other a problematic. Consequently we must start from premisses which are similar in form, as in the other cases.

同类推荐
热门推荐
  • 21岁房东的妖孽保镖

    21岁房东的妖孽保镖

    一场突如其来的意外,让他从普通人变成异能者,如同战神附体,拳打高富帅脚踢黑社会,美女纷纷来到他的身边,从此走上了妖孽的不归路
  • 下一世:谁许我一世倾心

    下一世:谁许我一世倾心

    那一世,你回眸一笑,我许你一生。这一世,你若安好,便是晴天。下一世,谁许我一世倾心?
  • 倾城无欢

    倾城无欢

    许你一世,还我一世,生生世世,轮回不止。未曾想过,我们的纠葛,绵延了七世。
  • 太极侠士传奇

    太极侠士传奇

    清朝初年,摄政王多尔衮为巩固政权,与天雷教教主于威雷相互勾结打压武林反清势力。天真善良的太极门弟子允道禅奉师命下山,遇到了种种磨难,也遇到了自己的红颜知己。在一番磨砺中,最终打败了于威雷,成为一代太极侠士。
  • 流浪的猫咪

    流浪的猫咪

    “黑猫”初识了流浪的金吉拉,开启了和金吉拉的冒险之旅,他们会受到各种波折,凶猛的野兽,友谊不断被拆散.......到最后他们能幸福到在一起吗?
  • 圣手医仙在都市

    圣手医仙在都市

    他来自乡村,为了那个普度众生的愿望,单枪匹马杀到了花花都市。他自负圣手医仙,无病不知!叶小豪,一叶扁舟却亦可豪迈天下!
  • 福妻驾到

    福妻驾到

    现代饭店彪悍老板娘魂穿古代。不分是非的极品婆婆?三年未归生死不明的丈夫?心狠手辣的阴毒亲戚?贪婪而好色的地主老财?吃上顿没下顿的贫困宭境?不怕不怕,神仙相助,一技在手,天下我有!且看现代张悦娘,如何身带福气玩转古代,开面馆、收小弟、左纳财富,右傍美男,共绘幸福生活大好蓝图!!!!快本新书《天媒地聘》已经上架开始销售,只要3.99元即可将整本书抱回家,你还等什么哪,赶紧点击下面的直通车,享受乐乐精心为您准备的美食盛宴吧!)
  • TFBOYS之洛溪苍颜

    TFBOYS之洛溪苍颜

    一个女生无意之间闯进了三个男生“平静”的生活,“对不起”这句话,究竟是对谁说的?“我们……身份差距太远……有些事……你不会知道”,究竟她的特殊身份,又会给他们带来什么麻烦?
  • 邪魅总裁:娇妻太惹火

    邪魅总裁:娇妻太惹火

    她无意撞见他的桃色八卦,从此结怨。“米伊伊你想逃到哪里去?”他戏虐的勾起嘴角,邪魅的眼睛微微一挑。米伊伊一个激灵连忙缩回脚,忐忑不安道:“我,我能不能不从。”他一个翻身将她压在身下,深邃的眼眸盯着她那双纯净的眼睛,性感的薄唇勾起一个弧度“你说呢?我的老婆大人。”
  • 樵史通俗演义

    樵史通俗演义

    叙述了明末天启、崇祯及南明弘光朝的历史。该书开篇即详细述写明代天启年间,朝廷内部阉党与东林党、复社之间的惨烈的斗争。该书所记明末及南明朝政,多为实录,当时有各种杂史如《两朝从信录》、《颂天胪笔》等可以取资,大体可信。