登陆注册
15489800000093

第93章

If one has made an induction on the strength of several cases and yet the answerer refuses to grant the universal proposition, then it is fair to demand his objection. But until one has oneself stated in what cases it is so, it is not fair to demand that he shall say in what cases it is not so: for one should make the induction first, and then demand the objection. One ought, moreover, to claim that the objections should not be brought in reference to the actual subject of the proposition, unless that subject happen to be the one and only thing of the kind, as for instance two is the one prime number among the even numbers: for, unless he can say that this subject is unique of its kind, the objector ought to make his objection in regard to some other. People sometimes object to a universal proposition, and bring their objection not in regard to the thing itself, but in regard to some homonym of it: thus they argue that a man can very well have a colour or a foot or a hand other than his own, for a painter may have a colour that is not his own, and a cook may have a foot that is not his own. To meet them, therefore, you should draw the distinction before putting your question in such cases: for so long as the ambiguity remains undetected, so long will the objection to the proposition be deemed valid. If, however, he checks the series of questions by an objection in regard not to some homonym, but to the actual thing asserted, the questioner should withdraw the point objected to, and form the remainder into a universal proposition, until he secures what he requires; e.g. in the case of forgetfulness and having forgotten: for people refuse to admit that the man who has lost his knowledge of a thing has forgotten it, because if the thing alters, he has lost knowledge of it, but he has not forgotten it. Accordingly the thing to do is to withdraw the part objected to, and assert the remainder, e.g. that if a person have lost knowledge of a thing while it still remains, he then has forgotten it. One should similarly treat those who object to the statement that 'the greater the good, the greater the evil that is its opposite': for they allege that health, which is a less good thing than vigour, has a greater evil as its opposite: for disease is a greater evil than debility. In this case too, therefore, we have to withdraw the point objected to; for when it has been withdrawn, the man is more likely to admit the proposition, e.g. that 'the greater good has the greater evil as its opposite, unless the one good involves the other as well', as vigour involves health. This should be done not only when he formulates an objection, but also if, without so doing, he refuses to admit the point because he foresees something of the kind: for if the point objected to be withdrawn, he will be forced to admit the proposition because he cannot foresee in the rest of it any case where it does not hold true: if he refuse to admit it, then when asked for an objection he certainly will be unable to render one. Propositions that are partly false and partly true are of this type: for in the case of these it is possible by withdrawing a part to leave the rest true. If, however, you formulate the proposition on the strength of many cases and he has no objection to bring, you may claim that he shall admit it: for a premiss is valid in dialectics which thus holds in several instances and to which no objection is forthcoming.

Whenever it is possible to reason to the same conclusion either through or without a reduction per impossibile, if one is demonstrating and not arguing dialectically it makes no difference which method of reasoning be adopted, but in argument with another reasoning per impossibile should be avoided. For where one has reasoned without the reduction per impossibile, no dispute can arise; if, on the other hand, one does reason to an impossible conclusion, unless its falsehood is too plainly manifest, people deny that it is impossible, so that the questioners do not get what they want.

One should put forward all propositions that hold true of several cases, and to which either no objection whatever appears or at least not any on the surface: for when people cannot see any case in which it is not so, they admit it for true.

The conclusion should not be put in the form of a question; if it be, and the man shakes his head, it looks as if the reasoning had failed. For often, even if it be not put as a question but advanced as a consequence, people deny it, and then those who do not see that it follows upon the previous admissions do not realize that those who deny it have been refuted: when, then, the one man merely asks it as a question without even saying that it so follows, and the other denies it, it looks altogether as if the reasoning had failed.

Not every universal question can form a dialectical proposition as ordinarily understood, e.g. 'What is man?' or 'How many meanings has "the good"?' For a dialectical premiss must be of a form to which it is possible to reply 'Yes' or 'No', whereas to the aforesaid it is not possible. For this reason questions of this kind are not dialectical unless the questioner himself draws distinctions or divisions before expressing them, e.g. 'Good means this, or this, does it not?' For questions of this sort are easily answered by a Yes or a No. Hence one should endeavour to formulate propositions of this kind in this form. It is at the same time also perhaps fair to ask the other man how many meanings of 'the good' there are, whenever you have yourself distinguished and formulated them, and he will not admit them at all.

Any one who keeps on asking one thing for a long time is a bad inquirer. For if he does so though the person questioned keeps on answering the questions, clearly he asks a large number of questions, or else asks the same question a large number of times: in the one case he merely babbles, in the other he fails to reason: for reasoning always consists of a small number of premisses. If, on the other hand, he does it because the person questioned does not answer the questions, he is at fault in not taking him to task or breaking off the discussion.

同类推荐
  • 戒庵老人漫笔

    戒庵老人漫笔

    本书为公版书,为不受著作权法限制的作家、艺术家及其它人士发布的作品,供广大读者阅读交流。
  • 随相论解十六谛义

    随相论解十六谛义

    本书为公版书,为不受著作权法限制的作家、艺术家及其它人士发布的作品,供广大读者阅读交流。
  • 文殊师利佛土严净经

    文殊师利佛土严净经

    本书为公版书,为不受著作权法限制的作家、艺术家及其它人士发布的作品,供广大读者阅读交流。
  • 蓬折箴

    蓬折箴

    本书为公版书,为不受著作权法限制的作家、艺术家及其它人士发布的作品,供广大读者阅读交流。
  • Bureaucracy

    Bureaucracy

    本书为公版书,为不受著作权法限制的作家、艺术家及其它人士发布的作品,供广大读者阅读交流。
热门推荐
  • 废柴王妃:腹黑冥帝看上我

    废柴王妃:腹黑冥帝看上我

    21世纪王牌特工不慎穿越到废柴之身。现在,当她变成她,她会改写历史,废柴之名永不属于她;她再也不是那个空有美貌却无一点儿实力的废柴,而且,她的美,再不会是原主那样娇滴滴的美,她将会惊艳四方成为人人为之仰望却遥不可及的最强修灵师!她会为原主报仇雪恨。她拥有圣灵体+炼丹师+六灵同修..........她还有多重身份:冥妃+沁香楼楼主+四界之首白傲云之女+.........
  • 旅伴

    旅伴

    梦境中的我也并非单独前行,在梦境中不以我的冷漠而无私给予我温暖的人们,谢谢你们。即使梦境的记忆消抹殆尽,因由你们,铭刻于心的温暖唤醒了我的复仇,我将与复仇并肩,我的旅伴······
  • 葵不向日妃向月

    葵不向日妃向月

    “你不可能找到她,就算你不爱我,那又如何”一女魅惑的声音回荡在六界之上“她是你妹妹,何苦你要这样固执,回头吧”抱着少女的背影,散发出无止境的杀气“你放过她,她是我姐姐,即使你是为了我,放她一条生路吧”奄奄一息的少女轻轻的叹息
  • 清代奇途

    清代奇途

    新的开始,新的人生。清代小子带领你走过官路,修仙,玄学,武学,各种各样的人生
  • 威行

    威行

    破碎的大陆,异界的位面,各族横行,群魔乱舞。神秘的宗门,诡异的际遇,兄弟齐心,诛仙屠佛。契约、天赋、融魂、格局、超越生死,一切,从这里开始
  • 恐怖之魔鬼游戏

    恐怖之魔鬼游戏

    这是一个名为魔鬼的游戏,一个可以满足一切的游戏。明知进入这个游戏的代价,人们依然不顾一切的加入。这是一个没有正义的游戏,那些好人却为之趋之若鹜。这是一个残酷至极的游戏,无数人进去便无数人死亡。~~~一个软弱的男孩进入这个游戏,会发生什么?
  • 娇妾

    娇妾

    少年将军席临川有两件事让他死不瞑目:第一,大战方兴,外虏犹在,出师未捷身先死。第二,年少轻狂,妄动凡心,爱的舞姬是卧底。但当上天格外眷顾于他,一切再次回到最初的相遇点时……席临川:喂!说好的美人计呢?!红衣:怎么古人也这么开放?!【情节虚构,请勿模仿】
  • 梦系列之梦境千年

    梦系列之梦境千年

    一个条神秘的短信,一个看似普通的包裹,到底隐藏着什么秘密。一个梦境,三世情缘,到最后是怎样的结局。敬请关注,梦系列文,给你一个梦幻之旅。
  • 寒凛纪

    寒凛纪

    简介:罗兰大陆,众神云立,一场不知为何的战争,众神陨灭,罗兰大陆也由此变成神墓……两千多年后,人类新生,大陆渐渐渐恢复以往的面貌,皇室少年,皇族的覆灭、亲人的离逝成就他一颗冰冻之心,面对昔日灭族仇人与战火纷飞、即将再一次毁灭的大陆。他又该如何抉择………
  • 神剑世界

    神剑世界

    吕布的后代盗窃?盗窃的时候穿越了?这一切都是迷。才怪。