登陆注册
15486800000071

第71章 4

Further, everything that changes must be divisible. For since every change is from something to something, and when a thing is at the goal of its change it is no longer changing, and when both it itself and all its parts are at the starting-point of its change it is not changing (for that which is in whole and in part in an unvarying condition is not in a state of change); it follows, therefore, that part of that which is changing must be at the starting-point and part at the goal: for as a whole it cannot be in both or in neither.

(Here by 'goal of change' I mean that which comes first in the process of change: e.g. in a process of change from white the goal in question will be grey, not black: for it is not necessary that that that which is changing should be at either of the extremes.) It is evident, therefore, that everything that changes must be divisible.

Now motion is divisible in two senses. In the first place it is divisible in virtue of the time that it occupies. In the second place it is divisible according to the motions of the several parts of that which is in motion: e.g. if the whole AG is in motion, there will be a motion of AB and a motion of BG. That being so, let DE be the motion of the part AB and EZ the motion of the part BG. Then the whole DZ must be the motion of AG: for DZ must constitute the motion of AG inasmuch as DE and EZ severally constitute the motions of each of its parts. But the motion of a thing can never be constituted by the motion of something else: consequently the whole motion is the motion of the whole magnitude.

Again, since every motion is a motion of something, and the whole motion DZ is not the motion of either of the parts (for each of the parts DE, EZ is the motion of one of the parts AB, BG) or of anything else (for, the whole motion being the motion of a whole, the parts of the motion are the motions of the parts of that whole: and the parts of DZ are the motions of AB, BG and of nothing else: for, as we saw, a motion that is one cannot be the motion of more things than one): since this is so, the whole motion will be the motion of the magnitude ABG.

Again, if there is a motion of the whole other than DZ, say the the of each of the arts may be subtracted from it: and these motions will be equal to DE, EZ respectively: for the motion of that which is one must be one. So if the whole motion OI may be divided into the motions of the parts, OI will be equal to DZ: if on the other hand there is any remainder, say KI, this will be a motion of nothing: for it can be the motion neither of the whole nor of the parts (as the motion of that which is one must be one) nor of anything else: for a motion that is continuous must be the motion of things that are continuous. And the same result follows if the division of OI reveals a surplus on the side of the motions of the parts.

Consequently, if this is impossible, the whole motion must be the same as and equal to DZ.

This then is what is meant by the division of motion according to the motions of the parts: and it must be applicable to everything that is divisible into parts.

Motion is also susceptible of another kind of division, that according to time. For since all motion is in time and all time is divisible, and in less time the motion is less, it follows that every motion must be divisible according to time. And since everything that is in motion is in motion in a certain sphere and for a certain time and has a motion belonging to it, it follows that the time, the motion, the being-in-motion, the thing that is in motion, and the sphere of the motion must all be susceptible of the same divisions (though spheres of motion are not all divisible in a like manner: thus quantity is essentially, quality accidentally divisible). For suppose that A is the time occupied by the motion B. Then if all the time has been occupied by the whole motion, it will take less of the motion to occupy half the time, less again to occupy a further subdivision of the time, and so on to infinity. Again, the time will be divisible similarly to the motion: for if the whole motion occupies all the time half the motion will occupy half the time, and less of the motion again will occupy less of the time.

In the same way the being-in-motion will also be divisible. For let G be the whole being-in-motion. Then the being-in-motion that corresponds to half the motion will be less than the whole being-in-motion, that which corresponds to a quarter of the motion will be less again, and so on to infinity. Moreover by setting out successively the being-in-motion corresponding to each of the two motions DG (say) and GE, we may argue that the whole being-in-motion will correspond to the whole motion (for if it were some other being-in-motion that corresponded to the whole motion, there would be more than one being-in motion corresponding to the same motion), the argument being the same as that whereby we showed that the motion of a thing is divisible into the motions of the parts of the thing: for if we take separately the being-in motion corresponding to each of the two motions, we shall see that the whole being-in motion is continuous.

The same reasoning will show the divisibility of the length, and in fact of everything that forms a sphere of change (though some of these are only accidentally divisible because that which changes is so): for the division of one term will involve the division of all.

So, too, in the matter of their being finite or infinite, they will all alike be either the one or the other. And we now see that in most cases the fact that all the terms are divisible or infinite is a direct consequence of the fact that the thing that changes is divisible or infinite: for the attributes 'divisible' and 'infinite' belong in the first instance to the thing that changes. That divisibility does so we have already shown: that infinity does so will be made clear in what follows?

同类推荐
热门推荐
  • 穿梭千年闯三国

    穿梭千年闯三国

    每个人都有一个不一样的三国情结,也有各自喜欢的君主、谋士或是武将,每个人的角度不同,三国这段历史的韵味就不同。
  • 柠檬味青春:我的王子殿下

    柠檬味青春:我的王子殿下

    (我们的青春,像柠檬一样,酸与甜不可分割。)他爱她,终将化于炽热阳光下的默默守护。她爱他,甘愿为他唤起心中被封锁的自己。一次年幼时的邂逅,注定了他与她的命运终将交织着。十六岁的重逢,他是玩世不恭的王子,她是别人眼中的灰姑娘。可是那又如何,两人在斗智斗勇中渐生情愫。可就在这时,一场巨大的阴谋席卷而来,友情的背叛,亲情的冷漠……随着一段青春之旅的启航,两人将何去何从?这是一个王子与灰姑娘的故事,也是一个高冷傲娇男孩与坚强乐观女孩的故事。(新人新手,请多多支持。女主自带萌点,并不是高冷哦!)
  • 芙蓉心计

    芙蓉心计

    我毫无预兆的,没有准备的,莫名其妙的穿了。可穿就穿呗,你至于让我这么背,穿到一个色狼的府里。你说古人没事这么聪明干嘛,我一现代人和你们斗志斗勇,我容易吗我。遇到不少帅哥,没一个敢碰的,哎。看女主如何玩转古代。
  • 时空执行者

    时空执行者

    她穿梭在不同时空,过着不一样的生活,她可以改变知道所以人的命运,却唯独不知道自己的命运....
  • 拨开那朦胧月色

    拨开那朦胧月色

    他说,如果我创造一种病毒,这个世上将无人可解。
  • 你曾许诺

    你曾许诺

    米小花是我的一个好朋友,确切的说是张若昀的好朋友的妻子,再说的具体些,那时他们来墨尔本,有过一面之缘,却都记在了心里。米小花和我,并不认识。只是有一天,孩子满月酒时,都叫来家里热闹,就坐在一起聊天了。我忘记和你说了。米小花已经是畅销书的作家,最近热播的电视剧就是她的作品,据说就连那些演员的衣服都是她亲自剪裁的。她送我一本她新出的书,插画很美,背景是一片淡蓝色的大海,中间靠着一对卡通的男女,很可爱。她说想要听听我的的故事。我随意翻看了几页,觉得文字的魅力太大,尤其是印刷体的铅字。某一天,我们重逢在咖啡厅里,听着窗外的雨声,就这样絮絮叨叨的说起了很多。那些关于青春,激情,友情,爱情和岁月。几个月后,我收到了一本新书。我看到“你曾许诺”几个字时就掉了眼泪。是谁曾许诺。
  • 武神魔主

    武神魔主

    无聊玩的一个游戏竟然变成了真实的世界,一个休闲玩家的异界旅程。
  • 穿越之一代商娇

    穿越之一代商娇

    她坚信:商之大者,可商天下——哪怕,在这个世界上,她只是一个孤女,也能凭着自己的双手,一步一步,闯出属于自己的天地!她以一个穿越者的身份,在重农抑商的大魏王朝,从一个失怙的孤女,成为举世闻名的女商,却痛失所爱,独抚遗孤,何故?她是两位帝王毕生的牵念,两代帝妃临朝称制,也都与她有着千丝万缕的联系,到最后她却只落得到大厦倾覆,流落海外的下场,何故?她是皇帝亲封的“一代商娇”,止瘟疫,平战乱,开慈堂,受无数人景仰,却被后世之人骂为祸国妖孽,何故?世事洞明皆学问,人情练达俱文章。且看她,如何成为那誉满天下,谤满天下的“一代商娇”!角色:女/商娇(杜怀瑾)、穆颜(胡沁华)、常喜、阿史那月等;
  • 重生的贵族

    重生的贵族

    作为一只重生的贵族,冷亦倾表示逆袭什么的实在是太简单了!只是......“报告,前方出现一只女主,请问小姐是前进还是后退?”“什么?遇到女主了!后退,立刻后退!”冷亦倾平生最怕遇到有病的女主了!而且她那么危险!还是后退保护哥哥为上吧!QAQ好吧,简单来说,就是一个心脏不好、作为炮灰党的贵族为了拯救哥哥对上了脑回路不正常的女主,然后被其生生气死,重生后发誓要改变哥哥命运的故事!
  • 叶罗丽精灵梦之世界公主

    叶罗丽精灵梦之世界公主

    本小说的主人公是和蓝孔雀缔结契约的陈思思在这本小说中思思叫亚希·思奇,是世界公主……