登陆注册
15416700000004

第4章

The action was not based, as it would be nowadays, on the fault of the parent or owner.If it had been, it would always have been brought against the person who had control of the slave or animal at the time it did the harm complained of, and who, if any one, was to blame for not preventing the injury.So far from this being the course, the person to be sued was the owner at the time of suing.The action followed the guilty thing into whosesoever hands it came. And in curious contrast with the principle as inverted to meet still more modern views of public policy, if the animal was of a wild nature, that is, in the very case of the most ferocious animals, the owner ceased to be liable the moment it escaped, because at that moment he ceased to be owner. There seems to have been no other or more extensive liability by the old law, even where a slave was guilty with his master's knowledge, unless perhaps he was a mere tool in his master's hands. Gains and Ulpian showed an inclination to cut the noxoe deditio down to a privilege of the owner in case of misdeeds committed without his knowledge; but Ulpian is obliged to admit, that by the ancient law, according to Celsus, the action was noxal where a slave was guilty even with the privity of his master. All this shows very clearly that the liability of the owner was merely a way of getting at the slave or animal which was the immediate cause of offence.In other words, vengeance on the immediate offender was the object of the Greek and early Roman process, not indemnity from the master or owner.The liability of the owner was simply a liability of the offending thing.In the primitive customs of Greece it was enforced by a judicial process expressly directed against the object, animate or inanimate.The Roman Twelve Tables made the owner, instead of the thing itself, the defendant, but did not in any way change the ground of liability, or affect its limit.The change was simply a device to allow the owner to protect his interest. But it may be asked how inanimate objects came to be pursued in this way, if the object of the procedure was to gratify the passion of revenge.Learned men have been ready to find a reason in the personification of inanimate nature common to savages and children, and there is much to confirm this view.Without such a personification, anger towards lifeless things would have been transitory, at most.It is noticeable that the commonest example in the most primitive customs and laws is that of a tree which falls upon a man, or from which he falls and is killed.We can conceive with comparative ease how a tree might have been put on the same footing with animals.It certainly was treated like them, and was delivered to the relatives, or chopped to pieces for the gratification of a real or simulated passion. In the Athenian process there is also, no doubt, to be traced a different thought.Expiation is one of the ends most insisted on by Plato, and appears to have been the purpose of the procedure mentioned by Aeschines.Some passages in the Roman historians which will be mentioned again seem to point in the same direction. Another peculiarity to be noticed is, that the liability seems to have been regarded as attached to the body doing the damage, in an almost physical sense.An untrained intelligence only imperfectly performs the analysis by which jurists carry responsibility back to the beginning of a chain of causation.The hatred for anything giving us pain, which wreaks itself on the manifest cause, and which leads even civilized man to kick a door when it pinches his finger, is embodied in the noxoe deditio and other kindred doctrines of early Roman law.There is a defective passage in Gaius, which seems to say that liability may sometimes be escaped by giving up even the dead body of the offender. So Livy relates that, Brutulus Papins having caused a breach of truce with the Romans, the Samnites determined to surrender him, and that, upon his avoiding disgrace and punishment by suicide, they sent his lifeless body.It is noticeable that the surrender seems to be regarded as the natural expiation for the breach of treaty, and that it is equally a matter of course to send the body when the wrong-doer has perished. The most curious examples of this sort occur in the region of what we should now call contract.Livy again furnishes an example, if, indeed, the last is not one.The Roman Consul Postumius concluded the disgraceful peace of the Caudine Forks (per sponsionem, as Livy says, denying the common story that it was per feedus), and he was sent to Rome to obtain the sanction of the people.When there however, he proposed that the persons who had made the contract, including himself, should be given up in satisfaction of it.For, he said, the Roman people not having sanctioned the agreement, who is so ignorant of the jus fetialium as not to know that they are released from obligation by surrendering us? The formula of surrender seems to bring the case within the noxoe deditio. Cicero narrates a similar surrender of Mancinus by the pater-patratus to the Numantines, who, however, like the Samnites in the former case, refused to receive him. It might be asked what analogy could have been found between a breach of contract and those wrongs which excite the desire for vengeance.But it must be remembered that the distinction between tort and breaches of contract, and especially between the remedies for the two, is not found ready made.It is conceivable that a procedure adapted to redress for violence was extended to other cases as they arose.Slaves were surrendered for theft as well as for assault; and it is said that a debtor who did not pay his debts, or a seller who failed to deliver an article for which he had been paid, was dealt with on the same footing as a thief. This line of thought, together with the quasi material conception of legal obligations as binding the offending body, which has been noticed, would perhaps explain the well-known law of the Twelve Tables as to insolvent debtors.

同类推荐
  • 佛说佛地经

    佛说佛地经

    本书为公版书,为不受著作权法限制的作家、艺术家及其它人士发布的作品,供广大读者阅读交流。
  • 传法正宗记

    传法正宗记

    本书为公版书,为不受著作权法限制的作家、艺术家及其它人士发布的作品,供广大读者阅读交流。
  • Just David

    Just David

    本书为公版书,为不受著作权法限制的作家、艺术家及其它人士发布的作品,供广大读者阅读交流。
  • 小室六门

    小室六门

    本书为公版书,为不受著作权法限制的作家、艺术家及其它人士发布的作品,供广大读者阅读交流。
  • 金丹赋

    金丹赋

    本书为公版书,为不受著作权法限制的作家、艺术家及其它人士发布的作品,供广大读者阅读交流。
热门推荐
  • 花千骨之爱恋重续

    花千骨之爱恋重续

    讲述的是花千骨失去记忆后,重新拜进白子画门下,过着美好的生活。放心,不是很虐
  • 霸气总裁的强大夫人

    霸气总裁的强大夫人

    陆展颜作为一个26岁的剩女,有时候真的得为自己的终身大事着想了,,这下子来了个闪婚,惊呆众人,静看她是如何阐述先结婚后恋爱的.......
  • 轮回仙决

    轮回仙决

    八道轮回,卷天地,破苍穹,三界之上,唯吾独尊!
  • 福妻驾到

    福妻驾到

    现代饭店彪悍老板娘魂穿古代。不分是非的极品婆婆?三年未归生死不明的丈夫?心狠手辣的阴毒亲戚?贪婪而好色的地主老财?吃上顿没下顿的贫困宭境?不怕不怕,神仙相助,一技在手,天下我有!且看现代张悦娘,如何身带福气玩转古代,开面馆、收小弟、左纳财富,右傍美男,共绘幸福生活大好蓝图!!!!快本新书《天媒地聘》已经上架开始销售,只要3.99元即可将整本书抱回家,你还等什么哪,赶紧点击下面的直通车,享受乐乐精心为您准备的美食盛宴吧!)
  • 冷皇戏凤

    冷皇戏凤

    她,穿越的第一天,便被她爹强行押上了花轿。行至半路,一声噩耗加喜讯传来! 新郎变死郎了,总不用嫁了吧? 谁知 “四王爷逝前遗命:婚礼继续,四王妃与灵位拜堂即可!且需为四王爷守寡一辈子,直到死!” 新婚之夜,被迫为夫守灵的她,却被一神秘男子,掳走。 暗夜中,她看不清他的脸,却听得他低哑而喃,“女人,记住,以后你是我的!” 凌雪漫杯具的人生从此拉开序幕,早晚三柱香,请求她的鬼丈夫原谅她被迫为他戴了绿帽子。 两年后,一个雷人的消息突然震破了凌雪漫的耳朵! 新皇四王爷莫祈寒登基了! 凌雪漫忧郁了,她男人真从棺材里爬出来了?
  • 穿越之激情人生

    穿越之激情人生

    犹如现实之中遇到之事,但却有不同,其中纰漏定然很多,各位书友看到不妨一提,在下尽量虚心接受。
  • 斯时芳华错景年

    斯时芳华错景年

    那夜,她洗净铅华,在车流密集的十字路口躺下。满天的星星,满城的霓虹,点不亮那双绝望的眼睛。再睁开眼,只见绚烂朝阳。没有庆幸,没有失望。她站起身来,拍拍身上的灰尘。尔后,转身离开……
  • 武迹

    武迹

    穿越者莫林突然拥有了一个系统,于是他发达了。为什么我突破这么快?因为我杀怪有经验!为什么我技能这么强?因为我技能有熟练!所有我的敌人都要当心,因为当你们算计我的时候,我却在琢磨怎么才能爆了你们。纵剑天下,快意恩仇,我就是武道奇迹!
  • 网络成瘾的心理学研究:认知和情绪加工

    网络成瘾的心理学研究:认知和情绪加工

    本书内容主要涉及:网络成瘾者的外显和内隐认知加工机制;成瘾者对情绪信息的初级认知评估和加工机制;成瘾者对信息的注意和记忆加工特点等部分。
  • 一生补处

    一生补处

    此世间有八大寒林:东方暴虐寒林、南方骨锁寒林、西方金刚焰寒林、北方密丛寒林、东南吉祥寒林、西南幽暗寒林、西北啾啾寒林、东北狂笑寒林。所有寒林都为弃尸之所,野兽妖魔啖尸饮血,尽享口腹之欲。“一生补处”的宦门之子王寂惺离家出走,卷入义军起事,被迫流放东北狂笑寒林。在寒林九死一生,王寂惺踏上回家的路,一路上饱尝乱世之苦,见证光怪陆离的社会现象,偶遇许许多多有缘之人,探寻人生的价值,苦觅世界的终极……